BREAKING NEWS

Jumanne, 31 Mei 2016

Normative ethics




Normative ethics is the study of ethical action. It is the branch of philosophical ethics that investigates the set of questions that arise when considering how one ought to act, morally speaking. Normative ethics is distinct from meta-ethics because it examines standards for the rightness and wrongness of actions, while meta-ethics studies the meaning of moral language and the metaphysics of moral facts. Normative ethics is also distinct from descriptive ethics, as the latter is an empirical investigation of people’s moral beliefs. To put it another way, descriptive ethics would be concerned with determining what proportion of people believe that killing is always wrong, while normative ethics is concerned with whether it is correct to hold such a belief. Hence, normative ethics is sometimes called prescriptive, rather than descriptive. However, on certain versions of the meta-ethical view called moral realism, moral facts are both descriptive and prescriptive at the same time.[1]
Most traditional moral theories rest on principles that determine whether an action is right or wrong. Classical theories in this vein include utilitarianismKantianism, and some forms of contractarianism. These theories mainly offered overarching moral principles to use to resolve difficult moral decisions.
·         1 Normative ethical theories
·         2 Binding force
Normative ethical theories
There are disagreements about what precisely gives an action, rule, or disposition its ethical force. Broadly speaking, there are three competing views on how moral questions should be answered, along with hybrid positions that combine some elements of each. Virtue ethics focuses on the character of those who are acting, while both deontological ethics and consequentialism focus on the status of the action, rule, or disposition itself. The latter two conceptions of ethics themselves come in various forms.
·         Virtue ethics, advocated by Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas, focuses on the inherent character of a person rather than on specific actions. There has been a significant revival of virtue ethics in the past half-century, through the work of such philosophers as G. E. M. AnscombePhilippa FootAlasdair Macintyre,Mortimer J. AdlerJacques MaritainYves Simon, and Rosalind Hursthouse.
·         Deontology argues that decisions should be made considering the factors of one's duties and others' rights. Some deontological theories include:
·         Immanuel Kant's Categorical Imperative, which roots morality in humanity's rational capacity and asserts certain inviolable moral laws.
·         The contractualism of John Rawls, which holds that the moral acts are those that we would all agree to if we were unbiased.
·         Natural rights theories, such that of John Locke or Robert Nozick, which holds that human beings have absolute, natural rights.
·         Consequentialism (Teleology) argues that the morality of an action is contingent on the action's outcome or result. Consequentialism theories, differing in what they consider valuable (Axiology), include:
·         Utilitarianism, which holds that an action is right if it leads to the most happiness for the greatest number of people. (Historical Note: Prior to the coining of the term "consequentialism" by Anscombe in 1958 and the adoption of that term in the literature that followed, "utilitarianism" was the generic term for consequentialism, referring to all theories that promoted maximizing any form of utility, not just those that promoted maximizing happiness.)
·         State consequentialism or Mohist consequentialism, which holds that an action is right if it leads to state welfare, through ordermaterial wealth, and population growth
·         Egoism, the belief that the moral person is the self-interested person, holds that an action is right if it maximizes good for the self.
·         Situation Ethics, which holds that the correct action is the one that creates the most loving result, and that love should always be our goal.
·         Intellectualism, which dictates that the best action is the one that best fosters and promotes knowledge.
·         Welfarism, which argues that the best action is the one that most increases economic well-being or welfare.
·         Preference utilitarianism, which holds that the best action is the one that leads to the most overall preference satisfaction.
·         Ethics of care or relational ethics, founded by feminist theorists, notably Carol Gilligan, argues that morality arises out of the experiences of empathy and compassion. It emphasizes the importance of interdependence and relationships in achieving ethical goals.
·         Pragmatic ethics is difficult to classify fully within any of the four preceding conceptions. This view argues that moral correctness evolves similarly to scientific knowledge: socially over the course of many lifetimes. Thus, we should prioritize social reform over concern with consequences, individual virtue or duty (although these may be worthwhile concerns, provided social reform is also addressed). Charles Sanders PeirceWilliam James, and John Dewey, are known as the founders of pragmatism.
·         Role ethics is based on the concept of family roles.
Binding force
It can be unclear what it means to say that a person "ought to do X because it is moral, whether they like it or not". Morality is sometimes presumed to have some kind of special binding force on behavior, but some philosophers think that, used this way, the word "ought" seems to wrongly attribute magic powers to morality. For instance, G. E. M. Anscombe worries that "ought" has become "a word of mere mesmeric force".[2]British ethicist Phillipa Foot elaborates that morality does not seem to have any special binding force, and she clarifies that people only behave morally when motivated by other factors.
If he is an amoral man he may deny that he has any reason to trouble his head over this or any other moral demand. Of course, he may be mistaken, and his life as well as others' lives may be most sadly spoiled by his selfishness. But this is not what is urged by those who think they can close the matter by an emphatic use of 'ought'. My argument is that they are relying on an illusion, as if trying to give the moral 'ought' a magic force.
Foot says "People talk, for instance, about the 'binding force' of morality, but it is not clear what this means if not that we feel ourselves unable to escape."[3] The idea is that, faced with an opportunity to steal a book because we can get away with it, moral obligation itself has no power to stop us unless we feel an obligation. Morality may therefore have no binding force beyond regular human motivations, and people must be motivated to behave morally. The question then arises: what role does reason play in motivating moral behavior?
Motivating
The categorical imperative perspective suggests that proper reason always leads to particular moral behavior. As mentioned above, Foot instead believes that humans are actually motivated by desires. Proper reason, on this view, allows humans to discover actions that get them what they want (i.e., hypothetical imperatives)—not necessarily actions that are moral.
Social structure and motivation can make morality binding in a sense, but only because it makes moral norms feel inescapable, according to Foot.[3] John Stuart Mill adds that external pressures, to please others for instance, also influence this felt binding force, which he calls human "conscience". Mill says that humans must first reason about what is moral, then try to bring the feelings of our conscience in line with our reason.[4] At the same time, Mill says that a good moral system (in his case, utilitarianism) ultimately appeals to aspects of human nature — which, must themselves be nurtured during upbringing. Mill explains:
This firm foundation is that of the social feelings of mankind; the desire to be in unity with our fellow creatures, which is already a powerful principle in human nature, and happily one of those which tend to become stronger, even without express inculcation, from the influences of advancing civilization.
Mill thus believes that it is important to appreciate that it is feelings that drive moral behavior, but also that they may not be present in some people (e.g. psychopaths). Mill goes on to describe factors that help ensure people develop a conscience and behave morally, and thinkers like Joseph Daleiden describe how societies can use science to figure out how to make people more likely to be good.

MCHUNGAJI JELA MIAKA 20 KWA KUBAKA


 



KENYA: Mchungaji ahukumiwa kifungo cha miaka 20 jela kwa kosa la kumbaka mtoto wa miaka 13 akidai alikuwa anamtoa mapepo kwenye uke.

- Mchungaji huyo alifika nyumbani kwa wazazi wa binti huyo na kumkuta mama mzazi hayupo ndipo alipomfanyia kitendo hicho

Ang'atwa uume na nyoka Thailand

Raia mmoja wa Thailand anaendelea kuuuguza jeraha katika hospitali moja baada ya nyoka aina ya chatu kutokea ndani ya choo na kumng'ata uume wake.
Attaporn Boonmakchuay,ambaye alipoteza damu nyingi amesema kuwa nyoka hiyo ilikuwa ikimvuta baada ya yeye na mkewe kujaribu kuipiga.
Madaktari wanasema kuwa Bw Attaporn ambaye alipoteza damu nyingi anaendelea vyema na matibabu.

Wafanyikazi walilazimka kukiharibu choo hicho.Baadaye nyoka huyo aliachiliwa na kuingia msituni.
Kisa hucho kilitokea wakati ambapo Attaporn mwenye umri wa miaka 38 alielekea katika choo chake nyumbani kwake huko Chachoengsao,mashariki mwa Bangkok kabla ya kwenda kazini siku ya Jumatano.
Wakati alipokuwa akitumia choo hicho alihisi uchungu mkali.
 
''Nilihisi kama ambaye uume wangu ulikuwa umekatwa,Nyoka huyo alikuwa akinivuta kwa kutumia nguvu nyingi'',alisema.

PICHA 6:Kutoka kwenye Mgomo wa Wanafunzi Chuo Kikuu cha UDSM


Ni Mei 31, 2016 ambapo Wanafunzi wa Chuo Kikuu cha Dar es Salaam wameingia kwenye headlines za kufanya mgomo wa kudai fedha za kujikimu katika matumizi yao ya kila siku.
Hizi ni baadhi ya picha kutoka Chuo Kikuu cha Dar es Salaam.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.


Samatta aiongoza timu yake kucheza Europa


Mshambuliaji wa kimataifa wa Tanzania, Mbwana Samatta ameingoza KRC Genk kufuzu kucheza Ligi ya Europa baada ya kuichapa Sporting Charleroi kwa mabao 5­-1 na kushinda kwa jumla ya mabao 5-­3.
Kulingana na gazeti la Mwananchi, Samatta, ambaye katika mchezo wa kwanza walionyukwa 2­0 alianzia benchi, jana aliaminiwa kuanza mchezo huo na kocha wake Peter Maes, akicheza pamoja na Nikos Karelis katika safu ya bora ya ushambuliaji.
Katika mchezo huo, Samatta alifunga bao moja na kutegeneza mengine mawili yaliyofungwa na Karelis ambaye alifunga magoli matatu katika mchezo huo, na Sandy Walsh akifunga bao moja kabla ya Sporting Charleroi kupata bao la kufutia machozi lililofungwa na Jeremy Perbet.
Kulingana na Mwananchi,Genk, ikicheza kwenye uga wake wa nyumbani wa Cristal Arena ilianza mchezo kwa kasi na dakika 16, ilipata penalti baada ya Samatta kuangushwa kwenye eneo la hatari na kipa Nicolas Penneteau, ambaye alipewa kadi nyekundu.
Samata aliwainua mashabiki wa Genk kwa kupachika bao la pili akiungamisha mpira uliotemwa na kipa wa Sporting, Penneteau katika dakika 27, kabla ya Sporting Charleroi kupata bao dakika 40 lililofungwa na Jeremy Perbet na kuifanya timu hizo kwenda mapumziko ikiongoza kwa mabao 2­1.
Genk ilianza kipindi cha pili kwa kasi na kufanikiwa kupata bao la tatu lililofungwa na Sandy Walsh kulingana na mwananchi.
Ushirikiano mzuri baina ya Samatta na Karelis ulisaidia kupatikana kwa bao la nne wakati Mtanzania huyo alipokimbia na mpira na kuwa katika nafasi mbili za kutoa pasi kwa Bailey au Karelis.

SOMA ZAIDI HAPA